Highlights
• Proposes a new cooperation-based theory of morality.
• Uses game theory to identify seven types of cooperation, and seven types of morality.
• Develops and validates a new self-report measure of moral values.
Abstract: Morality-as-Cooperation (MAC) is the theory that morality is a collection of biological and cultural solutions to the problems of cooperation recurrent in human social life. MAC uses game theory to identify distinct types of cooperation, and predicts that each will be considered morally relevant, and each will give rise to a distinct moral domain. Here we test MAC's predictions by developing a new self-report measure of morality, the Morality-as-Cooperation Questionnaire (MAC-Q), and comparing its psychometric properties to those of the Moral Foundations Questionnaire (MFQ). Over four studies, the results support the MAC-Q's seven-factor model of morality, but not the MFQ's five-factor model. Thus MAC emerges as the best available compass with which to explore the moral landscape.
Check also this meta-analysis of effects of helping on the happiness of the helper: The overall effect of kindness on well-being is small-to-medium:
Happy to help? A systematic review and meta-analysis of the effects of performing acts of kindness on the well-being of the actor. Oliver Scott Curry et al. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, https://www.bipartisanalliance.com/2018/03/meta-analysis-of-effects-of-helping-on.html---
1. Introduction
What
is morality? What explains its content and structure? And how is it
best measured? In recent years, the study of morality has become the
focus of a thriving interdisciplinary endeavour, encompassing research
not only in psychology, but also in evolutionary theory, genetics, biology, animal behaviour, anthropology, neuroscience and economics (Haidt, 2007, Shackelford and Hansen, 2016, Sinnott-Armstrong, 2007). A common view in this body of work is that the function of morality is to promote cooperation (Curry, 2016, Greene, 2015:40; Haidt & Kesebir, 2010:800; Rai & Fiske, 2011:59; Sterelny & Fraser, 2016:1; Tomasello & Vaish, 2013:231).1
However,
previous cooperative accounts of morality have not made full use of the
mathematical analysis of cooperation – the theory of nonzerosum games –
to provide a systematic taxonomy of cooperation. They have instead
tended to focus on a relatively narrow range of cooperative behaviours
(typically kin altruism and reciprocal altruism), and omitted others (for example, coordination and conflict resolution) (Table 4 in Curry, 2016).
Thus, previous accounts have attempted to explain morality from an
unnecessarily restricted base, and missed the opportunity to furnish a
broader, more general theory of morality.
The present paper has two goals. First, we use nonzerosum game theory
to provide the rigorous, systematic foundation that the cooperative
approach to morality has previously lacked. We show how this rich,
principled explanatory framework – which we call
‘Morality-as-Cooperation’ (MAC; Curry, 2016, Curry et al., 2019)
– incorporates more types of cooperation, and thus explains more types
of morality, than previous approaches. The current version of the theory
incorporates seven well-established types of cooperation: (1) the
allocation of resources to kin (Hamilton, 1963); (2) coordination to mutual advantage (Lewis, 1969); (3) social exchange (Trivers, 1971); and conflict resolution through contests featuring displays of (4) hawkish and (5) dove-ish traits (Maynard Smith & Price, 1973); (6) division (Skyrms, 1996); and (7) possession (Gintis, 2007).
Second,
we test MAC’s prediction that each of these types of cooperation will
be considered morally relevant, and each will give rise to a distinct
moral domain, by developing a new self-report
measure of moral values – with facets dedicated to (1) family values,
(2) group loyalty, (3) reciprocity, (4) bravery, (5) respect, (6)
fairness and (7) property rights – and examine its psychometric properties.
2. How cooperation explains morality
The
theory of Morality-as-Cooperation (MAC) argues that morality consists
of a collection of biological and cultural solutions to the problems of
cooperation recurrent in human social life (Curry, 2016).
Below we review the general argument, before looking at how specific
types of cooperation explain corresponding types of morality.
Life
begins when molecules start making copies of themselves. These
‘replicators’ are ‘selfish’ in the technical sense that they promote
their own replication (Dawkins, 1976/2006). They can promote their replication at the expense of other replicators. These competitive interactions have a winner and a loser; one’s gain is another’s loss; they are zerosum games (Maynard Smith, 1982, Von Neumann and Morgenstern, 1944). But replicators can also replicate in concert with other replicators (Dawkins, 1998). These cooperative interactions can have two winners; they are win-win situations; they are nonzerosum games. Natural selection
can favour genes for cooperation – that is, genes for
evolutionarily-stable phenotypic strategies designed to achieve superior
equilibria in nonzerosum interactions – and has done throughout the
history of life. Natural selection for genes that employ cooperative
strategies has driven several ‘major transitions’ in the evolution of
life on Earth, including the formation of cells, chromosomes and
multicellular organisms (Maynard Smith & Szathmáry, 1995). Natural selection has also favoured genes for cooperation between individuals, in a wide variety of species (Dugatkin, 1997),
including humans. Humans descend from a long line of social primates;
they have spent 50 million years living in social groups (Shultz, Opie, & Atkinson, 2011), and two million years making a living as intensely collaborative hunter-gatherers (Tooby & DeVore, 1987).
This has equipped humans with a range of biological – including
psychological – adaptations for cooperation. These adaptations can be
seen as natural selection’s ‘attempts’ to solve the problems of
cooperation. More recently, improvisational intelligence and cultural transmission (Boyd et al., 2011, Pinker, 2010)
have made it possible for humans to attempt to improve upon natural
selection’s solutions by inventing evolutionarily-novel solutions –
‘tools and rules’ – for further bolstering cooperation (Binmore, 1994a, Binmore, 1994b, Hammerstein, 2003, Nagel, 1991, Popper, 1945). Together, these biological and cultural mechanisms provide the motivation for social, cooperative and altruistic behaviour;
and they provide the criteria by which individuals evaluate the
behaviour of others. According to MAC, it is precisely these solutions
to problems of cooperation – this collection of instincts, intuitions,
inventions and institutions – that constitute human morality (Curry, 2005, Davies et al., 2014).2
Which problems of cooperation do humans face? And how are they solved? Evolutionary biology and game theory
tell us that there is not just one problem of cooperation but many,
with many different functionally, and perhaps phenotypically, distinct
solutions (Lehmann and Keller, 2006, Nunn and Lewis, 2001, Robinson and Goforth, 2005, Sachs et al., 2004).
Our review of this literature suggests that there are (at least) seven
well-established types of cooperation: (1) the allocation of resources
to kin; (2) coordination to mutual advantage; (3) social exchange; and conflict resolution
through contests featuring (4) hawkish displays of dominance and (5)
dove-ish displays of submission; (6) division of disputed resources; and
(7) recognition of possession. We briefly review each of these below,
and we consider how each type of cooperation provides an explanation for
a corresponding type of morality (Table 1).
Label | Problem/Opportunity | Solution | Virtues | Vices | Epithet | |
---|---|---|---|---|---|---|
1 | Family | Kin selection | Kin Altruism | Duty of care, special obligations to kin | Incest, neglect | Blood is thicker than water |
2 | Group | Coordination | Mutualism | Loyalty, unity, solidarity, conformity | Betrayal, treason | United we stand, divided we fall |
3 | Reciprocity | Social Dilemma | Reciprocal Altruism | Reciprocity, trustworthiness, forgiveness | Cheating, ingratitude | One good turn deserves another |
4 | Heroism | Conflict Resolution (Contest) | Hawkish Displays | Bravery, fortitude, largesse | Cowardice, miserliness | With great power comes great responsibility |
5 | Deference | Conflict Resolution (Contest) | Dove-ish Displays | Respect, obedience, humility | Disrespect, hubris | Blessed are the meek |
6 | Fairness | Conflict Resolution (Bargaining) | Division | Fairness, impartiality, equality | Unfairness, favouritism | Let’s meet in the middle |
7 | Property | Conflict Resolution (Possession) | Ownership | Respect for property, property rights | Theft, trespass | Possession in nine-tenths of the law |
2.1. Allocation of resources to kin (Family Values)
Genes
that benefit replicas of themselves that reside in other individuals –
that is, genetic relatives – will be favoured by natural selection if
the cost of helping is outweighed by the benefit to the recipient
gene(s) (Dawkins, 1979, Hamilton, 1963). So, evolutionary theory
leads us to expect that under some conditions organisms will possess
adaptations for detecting and delivering benefits (or avoiding doing
harm) to kin. This theory of kin selection explains many instances of altruism, in many species (Gardner & West, 2014), including humans (Kurland and Gaulin, 2005, Lieberman et al., 2007).
MAC predicts that because strategies for kin altruism realise a mutual
benefit, they will be regarded as morally good. This theory can explain
why caring for offspring (Edel & Edel, 1959/1968; an ‘ethic of care’; Gilligan, 1982), helping family members (Fukuyama, 1996, Wong, 1984, and avoiding inbreeding (Lieberman et al., 2003, Westermarck, 1994) have been widely regarded as important components of morality.
2.2. Coordination to mutual advantage (Group Loyalty)
In
game theory, situations in which individuals are uncertain about how to
behave in order to bring about a mutual benefit are modelled as
coordination problems (Lewis, 1969).
Humans and other animals use a variety of strategies – such as focal
points, traditions, leadership, signalling, badges of membership, and
‘theory of mind’ – to solve these problems (Alvard, 2001, Boos et al., 2011, Curry and Jones Chesters, 2012, McElreath et al., 2003), and form stable coalitions and alliances (Balliet et al., 2014, Bissonnette et al., 2015, Harcourt and de Waal, 1992).
MAC predicts that because solutions to coordination problems realise
mutual benefits, they will be regarded as morally good. This theory can
explain why participating in collaborative endeavours (Royce, 1908), favouring your own group (Bernhard et al., 2006, Gert, 2013), and adopting local conventions (Gibbard, 1990a, Gibbard, 1990b) have been widely regarded as important components of morality.
2.3. Social exchange (Reciprocity)
In
game theory, social dilemmas – prisoners dilemmas, public goods games,
tragedies of the commons – arise when the fruits of cooperation are
vulnerable to ‘free riders’, who accept the benefit of cooperation,
without paying the cost (Ostrom & Walker, 2002). This problem can be overcome by a strategy of ‘conditional cooperation’ or ‘reciprocal altruism’, such as tit-for-tat (Axelrod, 1984, Trivers, 1971). Evidence for conditional cooperation has been found in numerous animal species (Carter, 2014), including humans (Cosmides and Tooby, 2005, Henrich et al., 2005, Jaeggi and Gurven, 2013).
MAC predicts that because solutions to social dilemmas realise mutual
benefits, they will be regarded as morally good. This theory can explain
why reciprocity in general (Chilton and Neusner, 2009, Confucius, 1994), as well as its various subcomponents – trust (Baier, 1995), patience (Curry, Price, & Price, 2008), gratitude (Emmons, 2004), guilt (Gibbard, 1990b), apology (Ohtsubo & Watanabe, 2009), and forgiveness (Downie, 1965, Godfray, 1992, Richards, 1988) – have been widely regarded as important components of morality.
2.4. Contests between Hawks (Heroism) & 2.5 Doves (Deference)
Conflict over resources – food, territory, and mates (Huntingford & Turner, 1987) – presents organisms with an opportunity to cooperate by competing in less mutually-destructive ways (Maynard Smith & Price, 1973).
There are three ways of achieving this: contests (featuring the display
of hawkish and dove-ish traits), division, and possession.
Game
theory has shown that conflicts can be settled through ‘contests’, in
which individuals display reliable indicators of their ‘fighting
ability’, and the weaker ‘contestant’ defers to the stronger (Gintis et al., 2001, Maynard Smith and Price, 1973). Such contests are widespread in nature (Hardy and Briffa, 2013, Riechert, 1998), and often form the basis of dominance hierarchies where resources are allocated by ‘rank’ (Preuschoft & van Schaik, 2000). Humans have a similar repertoire of status-related behaviours (Fiddick et al., 2013, Mazur, 2005, Sell et al., 2009), and culturally elaborated hierarchies (Boone, 1992, Rubin, 2000).
MAC predicts that because hawkish displays of dominance, and dove-ish
displays of submission, together realise mutual benefits, they will be
regarded as morally good. This theory can explain why these two
apparently contradictory sets of traits (Berlin, 1997)
– the ‘heroic virtues’ of fortitude, bravery, skill, and wit, and the
‘monkish virtues’ of humility, deference, obedience, and respect – have
been widely regarded as important components of morality (Curry, 2007, MacIntyre, 1981a, MacIntyre, 1981b).
2.6. Division (Fairness)
When the contested resource is divisible, game theory models the situation as a ‘bargaining problem’ (Nash, 1950). Here, one solution is to divide the resource in proportion to the relative (bargaining) power of the protagonists (Skyrms, 1996). In the case of equally powerful individuals, this results in equal shares (Maynard Smith, 1982). Evidence for a ‘sense of fairness’ comes from non-human primates’ adverse reactions to unequal treatment in economic games (Brosnan, 2013, Brosnan and de Waal, 2014).
With regard to humans, rules such as “I cut, you choose”, “meet in the
middle”, “split the difference”, and “take turns”, are ancient and
widespread means of resolving disputes (Brams & Taylor, 1996). And ‘equal shares’ is a spontaneous and cross-culturally prevalent decision rule in economic games (Henrich et al., 2005) and similar situations (Messick, 1993).
MAC predicts that because dividing resources avoids a costly fight, and
therefore realises a mutual benefit, it will be regarded as morally
good. This theory can explain why fairness (Rawls, 1958) and willingness to compromise (Pennock & Chapman, 1979) have been widely regarded as important components of morality.
2.7. Possession (Property Rights)
Finally, game theory shows that conflicts over resources can be resolved by deference to prior possession (Gintis, 2007, Hare et al., 2016, Maynard Smith, 1982). The recognition of prior possession is widespread in nature (Sherratt and Mesterton-Gibbons, 2015, Strassmann and Queller, 2014). Humans also defer to prior possession in vignette studies (DeScioli and Karpoff, 2015, Friedman and Neary, 2008), experimental games (the ‘endowment effect’; Kahneman & Tversky, 1979), the law (Rose, 1985), and international relations (Johnson & Toft, 2014). Private property, in some form or other, appears to be a cross-cultural universal (Herskovits, 1952).
MAC predicts that because deferring to prior possession avoids a costly
fight, and therefore realises a mutual benefit, it will be regarded as
morally good. This theory can explain why the right to own property and
the prohibition of theft (Becker, 1977, Locke, 2000, Pennock and Chapman, 1980) have been widely regarded as an important components of morality.
3. Summary and predictions
Morality-as-Cooperation
(MAC) is the theory that morality consists of a collection of
biological and cultural solutions to the problems of cooperation
recurrent in human social life. MAC draws upon the mathematics of
cooperation to identify and distinguish between different types of
cooperation, and thereby explain different facets of morality. The
present review has identified seven types of cooperation, and hence
seven candidate moral domains: obligations to family, group loyalty,
reciprocity, bravery, respect, fairness, and property rights. Thus MAC
can explain why specific forms of cooperative behaviour – helping kin,
helping one’s group, reciprocating costs and benefits, displaying
‘hawkish’ and dove-ish traits, dividing disputed resources, and
respecting prior possession – are regarded as morally good, and why the
corresponding forms of uncooperative behaviour – neglecting kin,
betraying one’s group, free-riding, cowardice, disrespect, unfairness
and theft – are regarded as morally bad.
Starting from
these first principles, MAC makes the following predictions about
morality. First, with regard to content, MAC predicts that people will
regard each type of cooperation as morally relevant; that is, as falling
within the moral domain. Second, with regard to structure, MAC predicts
that because the incidence and value of these different types of
cooperation vary independently in social life (and are perhaps subserved
by different psychological mechanisms) the strength of endorsement of
each of the corresponding types of morality will vary independently too.
In other words, each of these seven types of cooperation will give rise
to a distinct moral domain. Accordingly, the theory predicts that moral
values will exhibit a multifactorial structure, varying on these seven
dimensions. Moreover, as a corollary of this prediction regarding
structure, MAC predicts that behaviour not tied to a specific type of cooperation will not
constitute a distinct moral domain. These predictions about the content
and structure of morality distinguish MAC from previous evolutionary
and cooperative theories of morality.
3.0.1. Moral Foundations Theory
The most widely-used, and thus far most extensive, attempt to map the moral domain is Moral Foundations Theory (MFT; Haidt & Graham, 2007) operationalised in the Moral Foundations Questionnaire (MFQ; Graham et al., 2011).
Like MAC, MFT takes a cooperative approach to morality, and maintains
that there are many moral domains. But, unlike MAC, MFT does not derive
its domains from any underlying theory of cooperation (Haidt & Joseph, 2011), and proposes only five: Care, Fairness, Ingroup, Authority and Purity.3
Like MAC, MFT includes domains dedicated to group loyalty (Ingroup),
deference (Authority) and fairness (Fairness). But unlike MAC, MFT does
not include domains dedicated to family, reciprocity, heroism, or
property. MFT has no foundation dedicated to kin altruism;
the MFQ does have two items pertaining to kin, but they appear under
Fairness and Ingroup. Nor has MFT any foundation dedicated to reciprocal
altruism: MFT places reciprocity (a solution to iterated prisoners’
dilemmas) and fairness (a solution to bargaining problems) under the
same heading, and the MFQ has no items pertaining to reciprocity. MFT
has no foundations, and the MFQ has no items, dedicated to hawkish
displays of dominance, such as bravery. And the only mention of property
occurs in an item about inheritance under the foundation of Fairness.
MFT
also includes domains – Care and Purity – that are not related to a
specific type of cooperation, and that MAC therefore predicts will not
constitute coherent domains.
MAC predicts that moral psychology will be sensitive to the benefits (care, altruism) and costs (harms) of social interaction
— for what is cooperation but a particular configuration of benefits
and costs? But, as we have seen, MAC suggests that there are different
types of benefits and costs — with different causes and consequences.
For example, some ‘harms’, such as murder, are considered morally bad
because they violate one or more cooperative principles (they break
implicit social contracts against the use of force, and constitute an
escalation of conflict, as opposed to its peaceful resolution). Other
‘harms’, such as punishment or self-defence, are considered morally good
because they promote cooperation. This perspective suggests that it is a
mistake to attempt to analyse benefits and costs in isolation, outside
of their cooperative context, by placing them in a separate, generic
domain dedicated to care or harm.
‘Purity’, meanwhile, has been described as the avoidance of “people with diseases, parasites [and] waste products” (Haidt & Joseph, 2004).
It has no explicated connection to cooperation; on the contrary, it is
regarded as an “odd corner” of morality precisely because it is not
“concerned with how we treat other people” (Haidt & Joseph, 2004).
By contrast, MAC suggests that the problem of avoiding pathogens (and
other disgust-eliciting stimuli) is not a moral problem per se;
instead, ‘pure’ or ‘impure’ behaviour is moralised only when it
provides benefits, or imposes costs on, others – for example, by putting
their health at risk. So, avoiding rotten fruit on a tree is not a
moral issue, but coughing in public without covering your mouth is. And,
because there are many different ways in which disgusting behaviour
might influence others – the problem of avoiding incest is not the same
as the problem of avoiding people with poor personal hygiene – MAC
suggests that it is a mistake to single out ‘purity’ as a separate,
generic domain.
3.0.2. Relational Models Theory
Similarly,
like MAC, Fiske’s Relational Models Theory (RMT) takes a cooperative
approach to morality, and maintains that there are many moral domains.
But, unlike MAC, RMT does not derive its domains from any underlying
theory of cooperation, and proposes only four: Unity, Hierarchy,
Equality and Proportionality (Fiske and Rai, 2014, Rai and Fiske, 2011).4
Unlike MAC, RMT’s domain of Unity does not distinguish between family
and group; Hierarchy does not distinguish between hawkish heroism and
dove-ish deference; and Equality and Proportionality do not distinguish
between reciprocity and fairness. Interestingly, like MAC, and unlike
MFT, RMT argues that there are no distinct domains dedicated to ‘harm'
or ‘purity’.5
3.0.3. Theory of Dyadic Morality
Unlike MAC (and MFT and RMT), Gray’s Theory of Dyadic Morality (TDM) (Schein & Gray, 2018)
does not take a cooperative approach to morality, but instead argues
that the function of moral rules is to minimise harm to others (and is
therefore a form of utilitarianism). TDM recognises that there may be
different “genres” of harm that correspond to MFT’s domains, but argues
that all moral violations are processed by general-purpose psychological
mechanisms, as opposed to distinct special-purpose mechanisms. Like
MAC, and RMT, TDM does not accept MFT’s claim that ‘purity’ is a
distinct domain of morality – indeed, TDM has marshalled considerable
evidence to suggest that ‘impure’ or disgusting acts are merely a
particular form of harmful behaviour (Gray, Schein, & Ward, 2014).
3.0.4. Side-Taking Theory of Morality
Finally, like MAC, DeScioli and Kurzban’s ‘side-taking’ theory of morality (STTM) agrees that cooperation explains moral behaviour: “evolutionary
theories of morality [that] focus on understanding cooperation…do an
excellent job of explaining why humans…care for offspring, cooperate in
groups, trade favors, communicate honestly, and respect property” (DeScioli, 2016: 23). However, whereas MAC would argue that these cooperative theories also explain why people make and express moral judgements – for example, to decide with whom to cooperate in future (Krasnow, Delton, Cosmides, & Tooby, 2016), to warn friends and family of uncooperative individuals, to enhance one’s reputation as trustworthy or heroic (Barclay, 2016), or to recruit allies to prosecute an offender (Petersen, 2013)
– STTM argues instead that the sole function of moral judgements is to
provide salient focal points around which people coordinate when taking
sides in interpersonal conflicts (DeScioli and Kurzban, 2009, DeScioli and Kurzban, 2013). STTM maintains that a wide range of content, including cooperative rules, can fulfil this function.
Thus
MAC makes predictions about the content and structure of morality that
are more extensive and detailed than those of previous theories. For the
remainder of this paper we will focus on testing MAC’s predictions
against those of the most well-developed theory – MFT – and return to
the implications of our findings for the other theories in the general
discussion.
Previous empirical research provides some support for MAC’s predictions about the content and structure of morality.
3.1. The content of morality
With
regard to content, an analysis of the historical ethnographic records
of 60 societies found that the moral valence of these seven cooperative
behaviours was uniformly positive, and that there is evidence for the
majority of these cooperative moral values in the majority of cultures,
in all regions of the world (Curry et al., 2019).
Research on more contemporary populations paints a similar picture.
First, a survey of family values involving student samples from 30
countries (Byrne and van de Vijver, 2014, Georgas et al., 2006) and responses to items in the World Values Survey, conducted in over 65 societies (Inglehart & Baker, 2000),
indicate that ‘helping kin’ is widely considered to be morally good.
Second, responses from internet samples to the Ingroup items in the
Moral Foundations Questionnaire (Graham et al., 2011), and responses from student samples in 20 countries to items from the Schwartz Basic Values Survey (Schwartz, 1992)
both indicate that ‘helping your group’ is widely considered to be
morally good. Third, endorsement of the norms of positive and negative
reciprocity in student samples (Eisenberger, Lynch, Aselage, & Rohdieck, 2004), in Britain and Italy (Perugini, Gallucci, Presaghi, & Ercolani, 2003), and responses to some items in the Values in Action Inventory of Strengths in 54 countries (Park et al., 2006, Peterson and Seligman, 2004) and Schwartz’s Values Scale (Schwartz, 1992)
indicate that ‘reciprocity’ is widely considered to be morally good.
Fourth, investigations into the concept of honour, among students in the
US and Turkey (Cross et al., 2014)
indicate that various hawkish traits such as bravery are considered to
be morally good. Fifth, responses to Authority items in the Moral
Foundations Questionnaire (Graham et al., 2011), and to items from the Schwartz Basic Values Survey (Schwartz, 1992)
indicate that ‘respecting superiors’ is widely considered to be morally
good. Sixth, responses to items in the Merit Principle Scale in student
samples (Davey, Bobocel, Son Hing, & Zanna, 1999)
indicate that ‘dividing disputed resources’ is considered to be morally
good. And seventh, responses to items in the World Values Survey
(reported in Weeden & Kurzban, 2013) indicate that ‘respecting property’ is widely considered to be morally good.
However,
previous research has not provided a full test of MAC’s predictions
about the content of morality; no previous study has investigated the
moral relevance of all seven forms of cooperative behaviour in a single,
contemporary, representative sample. Instead, the studies reviewed
above have measured different aspects of morality, in different ways;
the scales they employ typically measure something other than the moral
relevance (or valence) of cooperation (for example, they ask whether a
person or a society possesses a particular trait, rather than whether
the trait is moral); and the samples they use are typically composed
only of students.
3.2. The structure of morality
With
regard to structure, no previous research has investigated MAC’s
prediction that these seven different types of cooperation will give
rise to distinct domains of morality. This is because no previous
attempts to map the moral domain – even those that have argued that the
function of morality is to promote cooperation – have been guided by the
mathematics of cooperation reviewed above, and hence none contain all
of the domains predicted by MAC (Curry, 2016).
Nevertheless,
despite its limitations, it is possible to ask whether previous work
using the Moral Foundations Questionnaire (MFQ) supports MAC’s
predictions where the two theories overlap. Here the evidence is mixed. Factor analysis has provided only limited support for MFT’s five-factor model. The original exploratory factor analysis of data collected using the MFQ suggested a two-factor model (Table 2 in Graham et al., 2011).
Confirmatory factor analysis of this data suggested that MFT’s
five-factor model provided a better fit; but the size of the improvement
was marginal, and more importantly, none of the resulting five-factor
models exhibited a conventionally ‘acceptable’ model fit (CFIs ≤ 0.88;
Table 10; Graham et al., 2011). Subsequent independent replications in Italy (CFI = 0.88; Bobbio, Nencini, & Sarrica, 2011), New Zealand (CFI = 0.83; Davies, Sibley, & Liu, 2014), Korea (CFI = 0.68; Glover et al., 2014), Sweden (CFI = 0.68; Nilsson & Erlandsson, 2015), and Turkey (CFI = 0.78; Yilmaz, Harma, Bahcekapili, & Cesur, 2016), as well as a 27 country study using the short-form MFQ (CFIs ≤ 0.70; Iurino & Saucier, submitted),
all suggest a similar pattern. For this reason, an alternative
two-factor model – consisting of an ‘individualising’ domain of Care and
Fairness, and the ‘binding’ domain of Ingroup, Authority and Purity – is typically used in research (for example, see: Lewis and Bates, 2010, Smith et al., 2016).
Thus
empirical research with the MFQ does not support MAC’s prediction that
group, deference and fairness will be distinct domains; but it does
support MAC’s prediction that domains not tied to specific forms of cooperation – namely Care and Purity – will not constitute distinct domains.
However,
it is not clear whether these findings indicate a problem with the
cooperative approach to morality in general, or merely a problem with
the way that it has been operationalised and measured in Moral
Foundations Theory and the MFQ. After all, proponents of MFT have
acknowledged that the original list of foundations was somewhat
“arbitrary” (p. 107), based on a limited review of only “five books and
articles” (p. 107); that this list was never meant to be “exhaustive”
(p. 104); and that they “do not know how many moral foundations there
really are” (p. 58). And they have positively encouraged research that
could “demonstrate the existence of an additional foundation, or show
that any of the current five foundations should be merged or eliminated”
(Graham et al., 2013, p. 99).
And
so, in order to test MAC’s predictions – that there will be three
additional domains (Family, Heroism, Property), that Reciprocity should
not be merged with Fairness; and that Care and Purity should be
eliminated – and to overcome the limitations of MFT and the MFQ, we set
out to develop a new measure of morality, the ‘Morality-as-Cooperation
Questionnaire’.6
[...][Methods, studies]
8. General discussion
Morality-as-Cooperation
(MAC) is the theory that morality consists of a collection of solutions
to recurrent problems of cooperation. Here we have shown how the
mathematics of cooperation – derived from evolutionary biology and
nonzero sum game theory
– can be used to develop this theory; and by identifying seven
candidate types of cooperative behaviour, we have extended the theory to
incorporate and explain more aspects of morality than previous
cooperative accounts.
We have also tested MAC’s
predictions regarding the content and structure of morality, over the
course of four studies. Regarding content, the results support the
prediction that all seven types of cooperative behaviours – helping kin,
helping one’s group, reciprocating costs and benefits, displaying
‘hawkish’ and dove-ish traits, dividing disputed resources, and
respecting prior possession – will be considered relevant to morality.
And regarding structure, the results support the prediction that there
will be distinct moral domains dedicated to family, groups, reciprocity,
heroism, deference, fairness and property. In this way, MAC goes beyond
previous theories of morality, including MFT, to identify for the first
time novel moral domains of morality relating to family, reciprocity,
heroism and property.
More specifically, the results support MAC’s claim that (contrary to RMT) ‘family'
can be distinguished from ‘group’, and (contrary to MFT and RMT)
‘reciprocity’ can be distinguished from ‘fairness’. And the results
support MAC’s prediction that behaviour not tied to specific forms of cooperation (‘care’ and ‘purity’) will not form distinct moral domains (consistent with RMT, and RMT and TDM, respectively).
These
studies have also produced a new scale for the measurement of morality –
the MAC-Q – that exhibits broader and more detailed coverage than, and
superior psychometric
properties to, the previous leading scale. The results also question
the routine combination of Relevance and Judgement scales. As originally
anticipated (Graham et al., 2009),
the Relevance and Judgement scales seem to measure somewhat disparate
aspects of morality. Across three studies, we found consistent evidence
indicating that Relevance and Judgement items should not be combined
into a common scale without accounting for their differences. Until the
reasons for this discrepancy between moral relevance and judgement is
understood, we recommend either combining the measures using a MTMM
model, as described above, or using one or both scales separately.
8.1. Limitations and future directions
First,
the present study tested the general theory of MAC with respect to
seven specific types of cooperation. Future research search should test
the theory more widely still, using additional examples of cooperative
behaviour. These might include ‘subcomponents’ of the types of
cooperation discussed here; for example, ‘social exchange’ involves not
just reciprocity, but also trust, gratitude, guilt, apology and forgiveness.
Or it might include novel types of cooperation yet to be discovered or
adumbrated by game theory and the behavioural sciences. Such research
could extend MAC to other, as yet poorly understood, aspects of
morality.
Second, the present study found that even
though ‘care' and ‘purity' did not reliably emerge as unitary domains,
the items they contained were nevertheless rated as relevant to
morality. Future research should aim to explain why. Perhaps, as MAC
suggests, these constructs reflect the operation of proximate
mechanisms, such as sympathy and disgust, that contribute to the
solution of multiple distinct problems of cooperation.15
Third,
the present study has successfully ‘isolated’ seven different types of
morality. Future research should investigate how they interact. For
example, MAC predicts that having to choose between alternative,
incompatible cooperative courses of action will give rise to moral dilemmas. Should you tend to your ailing mother, or go off to fight for your country (Sartre, 1946/1973)?
MAC also predicts that when one cooperative opportunity is pursued at
the expense of some larger more valuable opportunity (‘the greater
good’), the former will be regarded as (relatively) morally bad (Muthukrishna, Francois, Pourahmadi, & Henrich, 2017).
And MAC suggests that these seven first-order ‘moral elements’ may
combine to form 21 second-order ‘moral molecules’ (and 35 third-order
molecules, and so on). For example, Family and Deference may combine to
form Filial Piety (Nichols, 2013).
Investigating how dilemmas arise and are resolved, and how higher-order
concepts emerge, could extend the explanatory scope of the theory
further still.
Fourth, the present study has looked for
invariant aspects of morality, in two English-speaking Western,
Educated, Industrialised, Rich, Democratic cultures (W.E.I.R.D; Henrich, Heine, & Norenzayan, 2010).
Future research should test this factor-structure in a wider range of
languages and cultures, and investigate how morality varies between
individuals, within and between cultures – especially, whether moral
values reflect the value of different types of cooperation under
different social conditions.
Fifth, reviewing the final
set of items, we note the possibility that some may be
less-than-optimally phrased. For example, it’s possible that questions
that use comparative (“there should be more X”), superlative (“Y is the most admirable trait”) or extreme (“you should always
do Z”) terms may be somewhat ambiguous, and hence difficult to
interpret. Participants may value X, but disagree with the item because
they think there is enough of it; they may admire Y, but disagree with
because they think it is the second most important trait; or they may
endorse X, but disagree because they can conceive of plausible
exceptions. This applies to MAC-Q items like “Society should do more to
honour its heroes”, “Courage in the face of adversity is the most
admirable trait”, and “You should always be loyal to your family”, as
well as MFQ items like “It is more important to be a team player than to
express oneself”, “Compassion for those who are suffering is the most
crucial virtue”, “It can never be right to kill a human being”. Future
research should experiment with simpler positive language, being mindful
of the ceiling and floor effects that ‘milder' items may produce. We
also note that the MAC-Q Heroism item “To be willing to lay down your
life for your country is the height of bravery” introduces a possible
confound with Mutualism, and should be avoided in future. In addition,
we note that the Division items focus on the simplest form of fairness:
equality. Future research should aim to explore other more nuanced
expressions of fairness, such as proportionality or merit, which can
lead to unequal outcomes (Starmans, Sheskin, & Bloom, 2017).
Lastly, the item selection procedure delivered reversed Judgement items
for Property, and for Property only, which may have introduced a
confound in the valence of the items. Future work should investigate
this, and if necessary correct it. Generally speaking, future research
should aim to replicate the present findings with alternative sets of
items, and indeed with other types of stimuli (such as standardised
vignettes) (Clifford, Iyengar, Cabeza, & Sinnott-Armstrong, 2015).
Finally,
the present study found that the MAC-Q’s psychometrics performed well,
and compare favourably to the MFQ’s, but there is room for improvement,
especially with regard to external criterion scales. Future research
should aim to identify external scales which ask questions more directly
related to the moral valence of the behaviour (rather than, as noted
above, asking whether a person performs that behaviour). Such research
should also extend beyond self-report scales to use performances on tasks, and behavioural measures such as experimental games.
9. Conclusion
Here
we have introduced the theory of Morality-as-Cooperation, and shown how
it provides a principled, predictive and productive approach to the
content and structure of morality. Using cooperation as our compass, we
have charted a new course, and drawn up a more accurate map of the moral
landscape – revealing familiar ground in greater detail, and surveying
previously unexplored territory. Thus equipped, with map and compass, we look forward to further discoveries ahead.